Children's Rights and the Philosophy of Childhood: A Generational Dialogue

Text
Read preview
Mark as finished
How to read the book after purchase
Children's Rights and the Philosophy of Childhood: A Generational Dialogue
Font:Smaller АаLarger Aa

Children's Rights and the Philosophy of Childhood: A Generational Dialogue

1  Imprint

2  A GENERATIONAL DIALOGUE

3  Preface and Acknowledgements

4  Introduction

5  The dialogue philosophic Approach

6  Children’s Rights: Between permanence and change

7  The mediation and enforcement of children's rights

8  I & You, static and dynamic childhood development

9  Questions and Answers at a Glance

10  Literature

Imprint

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.

Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.

Internet content: every internet and literature sources have been checked before publication. It cannot be guaranteed that all sources still exists but this does not change any knowledge and experiences provided in this book. A liability for any external source disclosures or references is alwayx exluded by the author.

Bibliographic information of the German National Library:

The German National Library lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; Detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de .

Texts: ©Copyright by Dipl.-Kfm. Werner Boesen

Cover design: ©Copyright by Dipl.-Kfm. Werner Boesen

Publisher: Dipl.-Kfm. Werner Boesen

Robert-Schumann-Weg 3

D-67251 Freinsheim

beratung@wernerboesen.de

www.wernerboesen.de

Druck: epubli a Service of neopubli GmbH, Berlin

ISBN: 978-3-748521-08-2

Printed in Germany

CHILDREN’S RIGHTS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF CHILDHOOD

A GENERATIONAL DIALOGUE
Statics and dynamics of humankind


‘I’ and ‘You’ are children of nature and cosmos, for the believers God’s children (Joh 1, 12; LUT)!

Preface and Acknowledgements

The present study was developed as part of a project at a German university and deals with the following the framework topic: Generations – Between Consistency and Change. My focusses centered on the first and second generation of being human , children and adults, and adults as parents. In my attempts to develop a basic scientific discipline, I discovered that there were many disciplines available here. The foundation of my analysis became the philosophy and integration of basic human knowledge of other disciplines of science, such as psychology, sociology, education, and law. In philosophy, I stumbled across a variety of sub-disciplines and I finally chose the childhood philosophy, a young research direction primarily in the American cultural space. In the German-speaking world, the term “child ethics” is commonly used, which refers to the moral behavior of mankind, and is therefore restricted to the general concept of philosophy which was limiting. Even the term “philosophy” in one of its possible definitions refers to the “love of wisdom” and gave me the direction for the following questions: What is love, what is wisdom? and what connects it to childhood in human existence? The framework topic in the project pointed me to a solid relationship, verbal and non-verbal, of generations, and their agility “between permanence and change,” for which dialogue is imperative. The anchor for this was offered to me by the philosophy of dialogue, a predominantly religious-philosophical subdiscipline that differentiates two people, as well as nature and the cosmos. This involves a twofold relationship, that of the ego (the “I”) and the thou (the “You”). It was also of general interest to consider the current legislation on children’s rights. The basic work and concerns here are the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child and their application within national constitutions, which only a few countries have implemented to date. It should be noted that the Convention on the Rights of the Child, not only in the philosophical sense, does not meet all the requirements of the child. This will be dealt with more comprehensively in the upcoming study, including a religion-specific view on the example of Christianity.

This project study was restricted to a certain number of pages. The specification was based on about 40 DIN A4 pages. It was extremely challenging for me to limit the content to this page specification and it is not enough that questions arise. I have therefore attached a questionnaire with possible answers for publication. It was also important to me to publish this work as both a German-language and English-language publication, as the childhood philosophy is underrepresented research publications in the German-speaking world.

In particular, I would like to thank the lecturers of the project study for their contributions to the discussion and critics, as well as Dr. phil. Laura Marwood for her assistance in fine-tuning the English translation.

In fond memory of my most recent childhood, I dedicate this work to my beloved Mother and would like to thank the private, state and religious communities for their loyal education experts (Loyal’ here means committed to pure doctrine. This excludes abuse. That should be synonymous with the term ‘education expert’, but the use of a thing carries the risk of abuse). The ‘I’ grows on ‘you’!

Introduction

The philosophic view on children’s rights includes the whole childhood. ‘The philosophy of childhood has recently come to be recognized as an area of inquiry analogous to the philosophy of science, the philosophy of history, […]’ (Matthews/Mullin). When examining the notion of childhood, one must take the various existing theories and cultural understandings into consideration. As David Archard contends, ‘The modern conception of childhood is neither a simple nor a straightforwardly coherent one, since it is constituted by different theoretical understandings and cultural representations’ (Archard 2015 p. 53).

‘The conception is a very modern one inasmuch as literature has treated of childhood for only two hundred years, and science one hundred’ (ibid.). Human history has existed in our modern understanding for 100,000 years (Diamond p. 209), and humankind is specifically characterized by childhood and adulthood: ‘Developmental science views childhood as a stage on the road to adulthood, and the nature of the child as impelling him or her to the achievement of the adult capacities […]’ (Archard 2015 ibid.). What we understand by childhood is a permanent relationship, an interaction with adults, and vice versa. The relationship is founded on communication and a dialogue between the child and adult, a dialogue between ‘I’ and ‘You’. Philosophical anthropology serves as a theoretical basis here (Philosophic discipline, in general the anthropology, see Lorenz 2014 in Brandt 2014 p. 470). A key feature is dialogue thinking, otherwise known as the philosophy of dialogue (Definition i.e. Hügli 2013 p. 189 keyword ‘Dialogphilosophie’. All citations from Hügli are translated from the German into English by W. Boesen for the purpose of this study). According to this philosophy, all humans assume both roles. ‘I’ is the active role and ‘You’ the passive (See Lorenz 2014 in Brandt 2014 p. 487). In the ‘I-You-Relationship’ the ‘I’ meets the other that is not only ‘You’ as a human, but can be also an object or God (Defined by Martin Buber, see Gessmann 2009 p. 333 Keyword ‘Ich-Du-Verhältnis’. All citations from Gessmann are translated from the German into English by W. Boesen for the purpose of this study). The knowledge of the experience of ‘I’ and ‘You’ ‘happens in this process empirical at the transition of I-telling in earliest childhood to I-suffering in puberty’ (Lorenz 2014 p. 489, translated by the author, German text: Das Wissen um die Erfahrung des Ich und Du ‘geschieht dabei empirisch beim Übergang vom Ich-Sagen in der frühen Kindheit zum Ich-Erleiden in der Pubertät). A precondition for ‘I’ and ‘You’ is rational behavior that is ‘documented in reciprocal delimitation [...] especially with rationale competencies’ (ibid. p. 478). Hence the child needs an adult as a reliable advocate. Where reliability and obligation involve risks of failure, this must be hedged by public law and observed by legal authorities. The following discussions deal with different childhood phases in dialogue context and will attempt to shed light on the main important dialogue-philosophical legal positions in the relation of childhood and adulthood. The United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child will serve as the basis for a comparison of legal positions (Commonly abbreviated to UNCRC.). Archard offers an analysis on this subject in his work with ‘Children: Rights and Childhood (‘[…] widely regarded as the first book to offer a detailed philosophical examination of children’s rights’, Archard 2015, first page after cover).’ The Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany is briefly discussed in relation to philosophic anthropology (see Lorenz, Kuno (2014) in: Brandt 2014 pp. 470 ‘Philosophische Anthropologie’…in general “Doctrine from mankind‘, p. 470 …reactive und reflexive discipline p. 471) and Dialogue Philosophy (See Hügli/Lübcke (2013): Dialog philosophy description for ‘dialogic thinking’ p. 189). A view on the 100,000 years of human history will indicate the archaic understanding of childhood. This study will finally explore the dynamic view of childhood based on the writings of late 18 th -century German philosopher, Immanuel Kant (main important German Philosopher, 1724-1804, see Gessmann p. 375)

 

The dialogue philosophic Approach

The dialogue philosophy (also known as ‘dialogicalism’ or ‘I-You’ philosophy) refers to the dialogue to the ‘You’ (Gessmann 2009 p. 168, Hügli 2013 p. 189). The ‘I’ is formed by ‘You’ (Gessmann ibid.). This relationship has essential importance and constitutes a fundamental experience of human life (ibid.). A human becomes a person through the ‘integration of I-role and You-role […]’ (Lorenz 2014 p. 476).

Dialogue philosophical basic concept

The word ‘dialogue’ and the personal pronouns ‘I’ and ‘You’ are the initial conditions of dialogue philosophical analyses.

The dialogue

The word ‘dialogue’ derives from the Greek and refers to a ‘communicative relationship between two persons […] to reach wisdom , […]’ among ‘persons who are aware of themselves […]’ (Hügli p. 189). Originally, dialogue describes the ‘literary art form as a representation of the Socratic dialogue Art’ (Gessmann p. 167).

A communicative relationship is more than a mere conversation. Communication means ‘doing together, taking part in something, talking’ (Hügli p. 488). It is necessary to differentiate between verbal and non-verbal communication, the first of which refers to the spoken word and writing, whilst the second form comprises non-written forms (ibid.). A dialogue always includes two or more persons. The word ‘person’ is used ambiguously (‘lat.persona, mask, character, role’, ibid. p. 681), and means ‘identification for the ‘I’, […] insofar beside consciousness […] owns a body […] has an individual history, […] develops into an own personality […]’ (ibid.). In addition to consciousness and physicality, there is relationship to a person from body and soul and the other minds (ibid. part 3). ‘Other minds’ are conscious states that belong to ‘other persons or animals’ (ibid. p. 303). ‘Person’ refers also to a collective, such as a society and state, called legal person, ‘insofar they have rights and duties’ (ibid. p. 681 part 2). Furthermore, ‘person’ can be used in an abstract sense, which is known as ‘personification’, such as the term ‘mother earth’ (Meyer/Regenbogen p. 490/491).

In strong relation with person, the term ‘personal identity’ is often used frequently (Hügli. p. 682 part 4 ‘persönlichen Identität’): ‘persons are changing, […] what does it mean if they are still the same person? What connects the adult with the child they once were before becoming an adult?’ (ibid). Does it mean in the dialogue the child acts in the person? The person is placed on an ‘immaterial substance (i.e. the soul)’ or memory despite of memory gaps or illusions (ibid.). The child has no relevance as person. Especially for very young children, the term person is clearly irrelevant, ‘[…] since typical criteria of some humans for defining a person (i.e. very small children […] are missing’ (Gessmann p. 544). The constraint only applies to very young children. Children are not generally excluded from being a person. The term ‘person’ is not fully describable and gives only an orientation that is normative in nature (ibid.). The term ‘rationality’ is also significant (ibid. p. 545). Due to typical missing characteristics describing human beings as people, it is helpful to ‘have an appropriate representative, […] for related regulation matters’ (ibid. referring Jürgen Habermas 2005, philosopher and social scientist, born 1929 Düsseldorf, see Gessmann p. 287). ‘Cultural norms that create solidarity also among strangers need to be accepted generally. We need to admit discourses to evolve such norms’ (Habermas p. 21, German text: ‚Normen des Zusammenlebens, die auch noch unter Fremden Solidarität stiften können, sind auf allgemeine Zustimmung angewiesen. Wir müssen uns auf Diskurse einlassen, um solche Normen zu entwickeln‘.).

The dialogue is personal in nature, ‘In a conversation, I will talk to another person who is addressed as You, and who also addresses me as You’ (Hügli p. 189). The conversation is also self-talk,’ […] if the individual is conforming to the attitude of the other, especially if these attitudes are shared by a whole group […]’ (Mead p. 79). In addition to personal dialogue, trans-subjective dialogue is also possible. ‘Trans-subjective’ means ‘beyond the subject (the ‘I’), also beyond consciousness, not belonging to a conscious process’ (Meyer/Regenbogen 2013 p. 671). This is a widespread view in the philosophical doctrine of personalism, which ‘considers humans […] primarily as active and evaluative persons’ (Hügli S. 683) and appreciates humans as ‘persons contrarily to a kind of potential objectification […] especially turns against any forms of reification of a human being’ (Gessmann p. 545). While personalism focuses on a person, dialogue philosophy acts on the relationship between persons, and accentuates the ‘direct character of these relationships’ (Hügli p. 684). An extension is made in theology, whereby personalism is explained with ‘a conversation between God as a person to humans insofar a human is facing each other and will be You for God’ (ibid.). God is ‘in general, an expression for a supernatural, attractive and challenging power that is either delimited or all-embracing and mostly imagined personally’ (Gessmann p. 278). The personal imagination of God is transcending personal reality and can therefore be called transpersonal. While in philosophy, the term ‘trans-subjective’ is commonly applied, the term ‘transpersonal’ is known from transpersonal psychology (Walach 2014). A main area in transpersonal psychology is ‘to explore and find those dimensions beyond self-development, also the spirituality that transcend sense and experiences like Being and Time’ (ibid.).

‘Spirituality’ means ‘intellect’ (Meyer/Regenbogen p. 623) with higher beings or something like soaring flights of intellect, and is a ‘popularized expression for the goal of searching not commonplace meaning […] also providing meditation and soft forms of religious enlightenment’ (Gessmann p. 681). The dialogue serves for achieving the truth that is the ‘description for the goal of everyone’s ambition for Knowing and knowledge and also a title for imposing a demand at least predetermined on any thesis’ (Gessmann p. 749). In general, truth is also a ‘determination of what is called truth in opposite to wrong’ (Hügli p. 935). There are numerous different descriptions of truth and truth theories (ibid. pp. 935-937, also Gessmann pp. 750-752). According to the truth theory of pragmatism, something is true ‘if it is fruitful or beneficial – be it from the point of life or science’ (Hügli p. 937). Furthermore, the consensus theory of truth expresses that something is true ‘if a potential endless big quantity of humans under ideal communications conditions will agree to a thesis’ (ibid.). This applies generally to national bodies of laws, such as constitutions. But these laws are also changeable. In summary, a dialogue is a verbal and non-verbal communicative relationship between the personal and transpersonal ‘I’ and ‘You’ with a view to reach truth.

The I

‘I’ is a personal pronoun and relates to the person using it. In a philosophic sense, the word ‘I’ is synonymous to the word ‘Self’ and has ‘no significant nuclear’ (Hügli p. 414). The ‘I’ is separate from ‘Not-I’, which is ‘a basic concept in the science teachings of Johann Gottlieb Fichte, (German philosopher 1762 – 1814 Gessmann p. 225), '[…]. In contrast to ‘I’, the world (meaning the transcendental external world of I) is built with setting of I’ (Meiner p. 454). ‘I and Not-I are terms of a consistent process, and in this process, there is a subject-object-relationship, in which both terms determine each other’ (Mead p. 53). The alternative condition is expressed on the personal base in ‘I’ and the other, the ‘You’. ‘For rational behavior, it is essential that the individual […] can also accept an impersonal position to become a counterpart as an object’ (Mead p. 266). Thereby, the other is addressed as both a subject and object. ‘It cannot act intelligently or rationally without being an object factor’ (ibid.). Other synonymous terms for ‘I’ include ‘consciousness, person, subject or mind’ (Hügli ibid.). The word ‘I’ serves to address other human beings, who possess consciousness, rationality and are understood as both a subject and mind. While subject is related to consciousness, mind is more complex and difficult to determine (Hügli p. 315, pp. 861-862 Subject).

Mind is ‘the universal principle, creating a relationship between human, God and the world. As a mind, a human goes out of the very natural being’ (ibid. p. 315). The word ‘I’ is therefore used both personally and impersonally. Cognition is needed in both ‘I’ and ‘You’. If a human cannot realize the own ‘I’, it is ‘You’ for the community. In the womb, an undeveloped being cannot recognize that ‘I’ refers to the self, and ‘You’ for mother and father, the family, the state, community, or faith. The term ‘Not-I’ is misleading, since an unborn child is already an individual. In the pre-natal phase, there are two individuals in one individual. Yet after birth, it takes time for a human to be able to recognize the own ‘I’. In psychology, the term ‘infantile amnesia’ refers to ‘the difficulty experienced by adults to recollect memories from the first two and three years of life’ (Knopf 2017). This phenomenon remains a mystery, since in long-term memory already exists in the pre-natal phase (Pinquart et al. 2011 p. 116). Potential reasons may include ‘a given underdevelopment of the brain, […] in early childhood with no relation to other brain content for a developed Self’ (ibid.). Even though the ‘I’ cannot fully recognize or is able to think rationally, it is existent in the sense of human being. ‘The ‘I’ arises from the social process itself and is not independent from this kind of experience’ (Mead p. 270). The ‘I’ can be defined as human being formed by many ‘You’. The ‘I’ of human being start with the ‘You’, I am You . As soon as I recognize myself, this sentence can be enlarged to: I am You and I am I.

You have finished the free preview. Would you like to read more?